I
Describing
the world is a strangely perplexing process. It feels as if it should
be effortless, but the more closely we seek to say how things are the
more we uncover our failure to do so. It is an outcome that philosophy
both uncovers and relies upon for its continued existence. No doubt it
is for this reason that poetry and philosophy, so seemingly distinct in
their approach to the world, find themselves deeply entwined.
Now
there are, of course, those who suppose that the task of describing the
world is in some way solvable, who think we can have access to, in
Richard Rorty’s phrase, ›the really
real‹. It is a
view adopted by many scientists and widely held in our culture and
embedded in the notion of progress and the increasing knowledge of
humankind. In the philosophical world it is characterised as realism.
Realist philosophers, and those who endorse the project to correctly
describe an independent reality, have tended to regard poetry as a
romantic flourish, a flowery plaything, while the true work of language
takes place in the realm of the literal. Poetry may express emotion or
create a mood, the emotion may be powerful and deep, but it has no
place in our understanding of the world and is secondary and dependent
on agreed and fixed meanings that we use in our factual descriptions.
In
contrast, in an article published just a few months ago and within six
months of his death, Rorty proposed that poetry was the source of the
imagination (Rorty, The Fire of Life, in: Poetry, Nov 2007), and
without imagination he argued there would be no new words, and without
new words, no reasoning, no intellectual or moral progress. Poetry is
the fire of life. By giving poetry a central rather than secondary
place, Rorty placed himself in a line of, what I shall call,
›non-realist‹ philosophers that includes
Nietzsche,
Heidegger, Wittgenstein and Derrida, and who between them have perhaps
been the primary philosophical figures of non-analytic philosophy.
Non-realism is not about the assertion of a different set of existent
things separate from the material which is prior or more real. Instead
it is a challenge to the possibility of saying how things are, a
challenge to our ability to speak of the really real. Unlike the
anti-realist, the non-realist denies the very possibility of an
ontology.
Each of these non-realist philosophers
provided
their own particular challenge to realism, and each grappled with the
puzzle of how to respond to the perceived failure of the realist
project. In each case they were led to place poetry or a poetic stance
at the centre of the philosophical endeavour. They did so not in some
romantic desire to escape the literal but in response to what they saw
as the failure of the literal to deliver philosophic truths about the
nature of the world. The attachment to poetry, as a metaphorical use of
language, is not an outcome of a wooliness of thinking, or a lack of
rigour, as critics have sometimes argued, but is the consequence of a
determined and unflinching thinking through of the realist project and
a recognition of its impossibility.
I do not intend
here to
rehearse the arguments against realism other than to note that realism
cannot get off the ground without a theory about the means by which
language describes or is hooked onto the world and Hilary Putnam, the
renowned American analytic philosopher, has described this project to
identify the relationship between language and world as being
›in tatters‹. Furthermore, at the outset of the
analytic
school of thought Wittgenstein in the Tractatus concluded that an
account of the relationship between language and the world is not
possible because the account would have to stand outside of language
itself. Non-realists maintain that in the ninety years since that
conclusion no viable realist response has been forthcoming.
While
the challenge to realism is substantial, the alternative is far from
evident. It is perhaps the difficulty of the non-realist
›position‹ – if for the moment one can
call it such
– that has enabled realists to pursue the metaphysical
project,
to say how things ultimately are, against the odds. For realists,
however difficult it is to form a viable realist theory, and all admit
its complexity, the alternative is notably less appealing. For
non-realism is seemingly at once embedded in a mire. If it is not
possible to say how the world really is, if it is not possible to
connect language to the world, how is the non-realist to find a means
to express any view at all? There are times when Nietzsche, Heidegger,
Wittgenstein and Derrida appear to be making claims about the nature of
world and of the human condition but on reflection they cannot hold to
any of these claims for were they to do so they would seemingly be
retaining an implicit realism. The denial of our capacity to describe
the really real would appear also to involve the denial of that denial
itself. Such is the non-realist predicament.
It is
for this
reason that the non-realist is led towards poetry. If we are not
capable of describing the world, such a claim cannot be made literally
without it being at once self-denying. For, if the statement
›we
are not capable of describing the world‹ is itself taken as
a
description of the world – which at first sight it appears to
be
– it is not possible to provide the statement with meaning
since
it denies itself. More broadly, a non-realist account requires a means
by which expression and meaning is made possible without it being at
the same time a commitment to asserting a given state of affairs. If
realists require an account of how language is hooked onto the world,
non-realists require an account of how we can have meaning and can
intervene successfully without access to the really real. Non-realist
philosophers would certainly appear to be trying to say how things are
in some sense even if they cannot do so directly, even if they choose
to describe this saying as playing in the language game, or exploring
our vocabulary, or unravelling the tradition from within. And it is
here that a poetic stance seemingly allows the non-realist philosopher
a space from which to be able to speak. A means of talking that does
not involve a commitment to the real. Hence Wittgenstein’s
remark: ›I think I summed up my attitude to philosophy when
I
said: ›Philosophy ought really to be written only as
poetic
composition‹‹
(Ludwig Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, ed. G. H. Von Wright, Oxford,
Basil Blackwell, 1980, p. 24e). Or Heidegger’s:
›Poetically, man dwells on this earth.‹ (Martin
Heidegger, Existence and Being, Vision Press 1949,3 p.312)
It
is
the late Wittgenstein and late Heidegger who find in the poetic
strategy a response to the implicit realism of their early works. It is
in his later work that Rorty advocates the poeticization of culture and
at the end of his life, after he is diagnosed with cancer, that Rorty
comments: ›I now wish that I had spent somewhat more of my
life
with verse.‹ (Perhaps the desire of young men to build
edifices
of thought is tempered by age, and failure.) TS Eliot, however, came to
the same conclusion, and for similar reasons, at the outset of his
career. He came from Harvard to study at Oxford in 1914 not as poet but
as a budding philosopher. Two years later, while still in England, he
submitted a dissertation, on ›Knowledge and Experience in
the
philosophy of FH Bradley‹ to Harvard as part of his
doctorate.
It was not published until 1964, less than a year before his death and
is remarkable for the way in which it prefigures relativist and
poststructural standpoints elaborated by non-realist philosophers many
years later.
In his conclusion Eliot adopts the
perspectival
stance typical of non-realism when he writes: »We are certain
of
everything – relatively, and of nothing –
positively.« (Eliot 1989, p.157). And goes on to argue, in
terms
that could almost have been written by Derrida a half century later:
»Any assertion about the world, or any ultimate statement
about
any object in the world, will inevitably be an interpretation. It is a
valuation and an assignment of meaning. The things of which we are
collectively certain, we may say our common formulae, are certainly not
true. What makes a real world is difference of opinion«
(Ibid, p.
165).
Eliot takes up a radical non-realist stance
providing a
critique not of material reality but the very possibility of things:
›The fact that we can only think in terms of things does not
compel us to the conclusion that reality consists of things. We have
found from the first that the thing is thoroughly relative, that it
exists only in a context of experience, of experience with which it is
continuous.‹ (Ibid)
These are remarkable
conclusions,
written two years before Wittgenstein wrote the Tractatus, ten years
before Heidegger’s ›Being and Time‹,
fifty years
before Derrida coined the term deconstruction and introduced the notion
of ›differance‹ and demonstrate the
sophistication and
originality of Eliot’s philosophical thinking (as Childs,
Shusterman and Michaels have catalogued in some detail). Just as
similar conclusions led Wittgenstein to abandon the attempt to make
general philosophical claims about the world, so we can conclude Eliot
was led as a young man to abandon philosophy in favour of poetry. Not
as an abandonment of the rational but as its extension.
II
Non
realism may lead to poetry but what is poetry capable of delivering?
Amongst non realist philosophers the strongest claims are made by
Heidegger who sees poetry as the means to approach an understanding not
available to us from the literal. For Heidegger, the poet is engaged in
the attempt to name that which is holy. Poetry allows us insight into
the essence of Being. ›… poetry is the inaugural
naming
of being and of the essence of all things…‹
(Heidegger
1949, p.307).
TS Eliot can be seen to adopt his own
version of
this strong thesis expressed in the context of the Absolute rather than
Being. Eliot does not claim that poetry can arrive at the Absolute, any
more than Heidegger supposes that poetry can reach Being, but in both
cases poetry provides a means to approach an underlying truth
–
even if that truth is itself ineffable.
Others
have explicitly
challenged this view seeing the claim that poetry can provide insight
into the essence of being as a residual hankering after the
metaphysical. Rorty, for example, in explaining his attachment to
poetry says: »This is not because I fear having missed out on
truths that are incapable of statement in prose. There are no such
truths; there is nothing about death that Swinburne and Landor knew but
Epicurus and Heidegger failed to grasp. Rather, it is because I would
have lived more fully if I had been able to rattle off more old
chestnuts — just as I would have if I had made more close
friends. Cultures with richer vocabularies are more fully human
—farther removed from the beasts — than those with
poorer
ones.« (Richard Rorty, The Fire of Life, in: Poetry, Nov 2007)
All
of the non realists can be seen however to hold the weaker thesis that
language is poetic in character. Rorty is perhaps most explicit arguing
for the poeticization of culture, by which he does not mean that we
should all become poets but rather we should identify the poetic
element inherent in our descriptions of the world and in our culture
generally. For Rorty the scientist, the historian, and the novelist all
use language poetically. They do so through the invention of new words
and new vocabularies to say new things. Although explicit in Rorty the
poetic character of language is implicit in all of the non realists
work. It may be expressed as an ambiguity of meaning, or an inability
to provide decidable meaning that we see in Wittgenstein and Derrida,
or in the poetic disposition of Heidegger, and Nietzsche.
There
is a fundamental difficulty however with both the strong and weak
thesis. As Rorty identified, the strong thesis that poetry might be a
key to a deeper truth appears at once to hark back to the literal, to
the desire for a metaphysical reality. While the weak thesis, is less
evidently perhaps but nevertheless, equally challenged. For how are we
to understand this poetic stance? We cannot of course take it to be a
claim about the nature of language, a literal description of a true
state of affairs: namely that language is poetic in character. As if we
have in this understanding a quick glimpse into the really real. As if
we have caught site of the true nature of language and, implicitly,
what it is to be human. But if the poetic stance is not asserting
something about the nature of language in what does it consist? Where
is Rorty’s theory of meaning that enables him to give us an
account of how we are to understand his claims that are not claims, his
descriptions of our circumstances which are not such descriptions, and
which provides us with an explanation of the means by which language as
poetry is able to generate specific meaning?
As I
understand it,
Rorty’s reply is that we find ourselves at a particular
juncture,
with a particular vocabulary and its set of literal metaphors, and as
such we do not need an explanation to understand what he is saying.
Such a reply however seems to me to have already provided the
explanation, has already given us our metaphysics, with which we can
interpret Rorty’s perspective. As with those he describes as
being engaged in ironist theory, Rorty wishes to provide us with a
perspective which denies the possibility of authority. Recognising the
reflexive problems of such a proposal his solution is to opt out of the
literal in favour of the poetic. The problem with such an approach is
that if such a solution was a solution it is not clear how he could not
tell us about it.
A similar critique can be made of
the later
Wittgenstein and Derrida. What is unique about Eliot is that unlike his
fellow non-realists, Eliot abandons philosophy early in his career
– one must suppose for these very reasons – and
devotes his
life to poetry and criticism. In doing so Eliot prefigures
Wittgenstein’s notion of language as use and
Rorty’s
pragmatism but in contrast with them the impossibility of objective
truth is precisely what drives Eliot to a pursuit of a paradoxical
Absolute. Eliot’s references to the Absolute are of course in
the
context of FH Bradley’s Hegelian notions of the Absolute but
his
arguments are strangely contemporary:
»(…)
›objective‹ truth is a relative truth: all that
we care
about is how it works; it makes no difference whether a thing really is
green or blue, so long as everyone behaves toward it on the belief that
it is green and blue. (…) And this emphasis upon practice
– upon the relativity and the instrumentality of knowledge
– is what impels us toward the Absolute.« (TS
Eliot,
Knowledge and Experience in the Philosophy of FH Bradley, Columbia
University Press1989, p. 168)
»And furthermore no
judgment is
true until you understand it; and you never wholly understand it;
because ›understanding‹ experience means merely
knowing
how to use it; so that what we actually know of a judgment is not its
truth but its utility (and truth never is utility). That at which we
aim is the real as such; and the real as such is not an
object.«
(Ibid, p. 167)
Eliot does not therefore give up the
attempt to
say how things are, even though he is convinced of the impossibility of
being able to do so. In this respect he has more in common with
Heidegger than with Wittgenstein, Rorty or Derrida. Those who argue for
the end of metaphysics may be tempted to dismiss this approach as a
task worthy of Don Quixote. Eliot’s defence must be that
metaphysics are unavoidable, that Wittgensteinian silence, Derridian
unravelling and deconstruction, and Rortyesque poeticization, cannot
eradicate a residual ›position‹ while still
retaining
content. The denial of metaphysics is itself metaphysical. And it is
for this reason that we have to continue to pursue the real even though
we know, I use the word with caution, that the real is not achievable.
III
Of
the non-realists Eliot is in many respects the most radical. His
critique of the possibility of objective truth leads him to give up
philosophy and devote his life to poetry and the pursuit of
›the
real‹. The question to consider is to what extent Eliot is
successful with his radical poetic strategy. In response to this
question, I’m going to focus on The Four Quartets as
Eliot’s most evident attempt to approach philosophical
truths,
albeit that they are at once not truths.
In these
poems
I’m going to argue that Eliot does to a remarkable degree
succeed
in approaching something that we might be tempted to call an underlying
truth. He does not of course do so by stating a position but allows the
text to propose an insight only almost at once to undermine its own
pretensions and thereby leave us with a notion that we have passed
close by to somewhere that cannot be named. In this manoeuvring there
are certainly echoes of the later Heidegger but with a greater sense of
illusion and of unstated strangeness.
In the short
space
available I can only provide a limited indication of this success. Of
course I also risk appearing to say straight-forwardly what Eliot is so
careful to avoid saying directly, or at all. My description should be
taken therefore not as a description but as a temporary way of holding
the Quartets which may help to explain my judgment as to their success.
One
of the central themes in the Four Quartets is the nature of time. Eliot
offers us a number of alternative stories about time each with their
own linked set of metaphors. There is time as the momentary present:
the shaft of sunlight in which we spend our lives. There is time as
passage: the river we flow along. And time as the sea, time as it
stretches before and after the moment of the present, out to the edges
of the beginning and the end. I want to suggest that we approach these
perspectives on time as precise descriptions of our experience and of
reality rather than supposing them to be a poetic flourish. We find
ourselves in the moment of the present, a present from which we cannot
escape, a present which provides everything that there is. Yet we are
also in the ocean of time, part, we might say in the context of the
Einsteinian story, of four dimensional space time. Our lives, our
civilization an inconsequential eddy in the vastness of this ocean. And
between these two static poles there is time as movement, as coming and
going, as becoming and passing away.
Each of these
perspectives on time are attempts to describe how it is to be alive.
Yet time is all of these seemingly incompatible things. And where
Eliot’s poetic and philosophic brilliance comes to the fore
is
his ability to be able both to describe with fine precision each of
these perspectives but at the same time to illustrate the inherent
strangeness and paradox of each description so that we cannot be
content with having understood but have instead a sense of having
passed close by to a truth which if examined closely would be seen to
be illusory.
Take for example one of these
perspectives in a
little more detail. Time as the momentary present. This is the moment
of subjectivity, the moment of experience. It is the moment we can
always point to as ›now‹. It is a strange place
this
momentary present despite the fact that we spend our time there. For
here we are now. In this now together. There is nothing else at this
moment for us than the now. Memories can be part of this present but
they do not give us access to the past and are instead hazy versions of
a previous present held in the now. The past a memory, the future an
imaginary space, we have only the present. Yet this present that is at
once all that we have, is also somehow wafer thin, almost without
substance.
Eliot describes this present in his
famous phrase
»the still point of the turning world«. Still,
because in
the momentary present there is no movement. Movement only happens
between moments of the present. The world outside of the present turns,
but the moment is still. If there was movement within the momentary
present it would have duration and could be subdivided into shorter
instants. It was this paradox that Zeno relied upon to argue against
instants and in favour of the One. It is a paradox that many believe we
have now excised with Cantor’s notion of infinity but in
doing so
we replace the paradox of the present with the paradox embedded in the
notion of infinity itself. Within the phrase ›the still
point of
the turning world‹ Eliot has already incorporated an
essential
strangeness, an ineffability to a description of the now. The
description contains its contradiction. The present is still yet the
world, of which it is part, turns. Yet despite, or perhaps even because
of, the contradiction we have sense of understanding what Eliot is
seeking to say.
Eliot goes on to describe this
present as
›Neither flesh nor fleshless; Neither from nor
towards‹.
It is the same strategy of internal contradiction, but this is not
empty poetic rhetoric. The present is not flesh in the sense that it is
not of the physical. The wafer thin present of experience has no
corporeality. It is not of the body. Pure subjectivity is somehow
ethereal. And yet, it is not empty, it is not fleshless. It has content
and distinguishes itself as being itself. Nor is there sense of
direction in the present. In the moment of the present there is no
sense of being caused by the past, it is just itself. Nor does it cause
any subsequent present. We are simply here, now, in the moment. A
strangeness that Hume so extensively grappled with. So
Eliot’s
description of the present: ›Neither flesh, nor fleshless;
Neither from nor towards‹, is a precise and accurate
description, but is expressed in a contradictory manner. Here Eliot
offers us what we might imagine is a glimpse of the Absolute, of how
things really are, and he tries to get as close as possible, to be as
precise as possible, but at the same time to express this precision in
a way which undermines the notion that the Absolute has been described,
for the description is at once something that cannot be fully held
because it does not allow for a resting point.
Now
you might
wish to argue that Eliot is here relying on different meanings of the
word ›flesh‹, and that the seeming contradiction
is in
fact a poetic creation. Instead we can see Eliot using these words to
highlight the limitation of all description. There is no literal
meaning accessible for Eliot just as there is no literal meaning for
Derrida. Meaning is undecidable and we operate in the play of language.
Eliot seeks to draw our attention to the limitation of our vocabulary
by highlighting its contradiction and thereby the strangeness of our
predicament. In offering us a precise description and at the same time
undermining this description in each phrase, and as a whole, Eliot
gives us a sense of the having glimpsed the Absolute and at the same
time demonstrates that such a glimpse is illusory. In this play the
reader has the impression of having caught sight of something about the
nature of the world and our place in it. Not because of the accuracy of
the description, or because of the deliberate undermining of that
description, but in the search after accuracy and its failure.
In
subsequent phrases Eliot reasserts this account of the present,
repeating its paradox in new forms:
…At
the still point, there the dance is,
But neither arrest nor
movement. And do not call it fixity,
Where past and future are
gathered. Neither movement from nor towards,
Neither ascent
nor decline.
And
then Eliot reminds us that this strange ineffable present, this stuff
of paradox, is all that we have even though it is at the same time no
thing.
Except for the point, the still point,
There would be no
dance, and there is only the dance.
One
way of understanding Eliot’s underlying strategy is a means
to
avoid the text becoming static. He describes precisely but in such a
manner that the description cannot be held. Contradiction is only one
of his tools to achieve this outcome. More broadly his text is a moving
raft of metaphor that evades all capture. We can see the example of the
momentary present repeated throughout the Quartets, both in specific
phrases and sentences that offer and undermine themselves in the one
gesture, and as a whole in the way that the poems develop and refer
back to previous metaphors only to use them in a new context and
thereby deepen the previous offering and undermine that offering.
As
a philosopher Eliot argued: »The Absolute, we find, does not
fall
within any of the classes of objects: it is neither real nor unreal nor
imaginary.« (TS Eliot, Knowledge and Experience, p.168)
As
a poet he abandons this attempt to philosophically describe our
circumstances and instead avoids offering any description which can be
held as such. Eliot describes this process himself in a later Quartet:
So
here I am, in the middle way, having had twenty years –
Twenty
years largely wasted, the years of l’entre deux guerres
–
Trying to learn to use words, and every attempt
Is
a wholly new start, and a different kind of failure
Because
one has only learnt to get the better of words .
For the
thing one no longer has to say, or the way in which
One is no
longer disposed to say it.
Again
it will be apparent that this is no mere rhetorical poetic remark but a
precise description of Eliot’s predicament. And it is of
course
at once the non-realist predicament. Here is a sentiment that could for
example equally apply to Derrida’s canon, and to which
Derrida
himself would surely approve. If meaning is undecidable it cannot be
expressed as such. Derrida offers us a variety of terms to explicate
our circumstances: deconstruction, absence, difference, trace, each
adopted and abandoned in turn. His continual reinvention of his own
vocabulary is one of the means he has used to seek to overcome the
self-referential aporia engendered by non-realism. Eliot sums up this
predicament with poetic brevity: ›one has only learnt to get
the
better of words for the thing one no longer has to say‹. A
description which at once applies to itself, thereby providing insight
and undermining that insight in the same gesture. It is in this
movement of an approach to a truth and the abandonment of that truth
that we have a sense of falling and being close to something deeper.
IV
The
literal and the poetic appear distinct. The literal is precise,
defined, capable of confirmation or refutation. The poetic is
metaphorical, elusive, and cannot be corrected. The one offers a
description of the world which might be thought to be true or false,
the other does not invite such judgment. The poetic strategy appears as
an abandonment of the literal, an abandonment of the attempt to
describe the world. It is an abandonment that leads Wittgenstein to
silence on matters metaphysical.
The literal
however has
always already failed. It is at once poetic. While the poetic requires
the literal. Literal prose and poetic expression are not two opposites
but two ends of a spectrum. If we seek to be literal and therefore
precise and exact in our descriptions we uncover our inability to do
so. If we seek to be purely poetic we find ourselves dependent on the
descriptive and mundane.
Now in my own way I have
struggled
with the non realist predicament, and my last book
›Closure‹ tried to rework the problems of
non-realism in
the context of the vocabulary of openness and closure. This vocabulary,
it seems to me, may be helpful in casting light on the relationship
between the literal and the poetic.
In the
vocabulary of
openness and closure, we close the openness that is the world. Through
the process of closure we create sameness out of difference, and in
doing so realise the differentiation, the identities, the things, that
enable us to intervene in the world, to achieve and do things, in short
to survive. But these closures do not enable us to intervene in the
world by being, or describing, openness. Closure is not a
categorisation or patterning of openness, instead each closure is a way
of holding the world that realises new material and new texture. We
can, for example, hold our current perceptual visual field in many
potential ways, themselves containing countless further potential
identities but none of these are, or approach, openness. Any more than
when we hold the stars as constellations, the constellations are a
description of what is ultimately there, as if Orion or the Plough are
somehow out there in the universe. And in the same way, our everyday
world of people, houses and cars, tables and chairs, are closures that
hold the openness of the world in a certain way rather than being
descriptions of how things are.
In this context, the
pursuit of
the literal is the pursuit of a final or complete closure, the pursuit
of a description that will not require any further revision. While the
poetic is the pursuit of openness and the evasion of closure. In
neither case can they be successful. When examined the closure offered
by the literal will be flawed. The scientific enterprise must in this
sense have no end, for it will always require further closures to
counter the failures of the current ones. And in some sense it never
comes any closer to openness for the gap is always almost everything.
While the poetic cannot evade closure while still having content. The
ultimate poetic gesture would be silence – a philosophical
strategy adopted not only by Wittgenstein but by many religious
individuals – but then silence is not a poem.
Perhaps
this is what Eliot meant when he writes in Burnt Norton:
Words
move, music moves
Only in time; but that which is only living
Can
only die. Words, after speech, reach
Into the silence.
In
his philosophical writing Eliot explicitly identifies our inability to
say how things are, our inability to capture openness with our closures.
»We
all recognise the world as the same ›that‹; it is
when we
attempt to describe it that our worlds fall apart, for as we have seen,
the same ›that‹ can only persist through a
limited range
of whatness. But just as we all admit the world to be the same world,
though we cannot specify in precisely what respects, for there are no
precise respects, so we feel that there are truths valid for this
world, though we do not know what these truths are. The true critic is
a scrupulous avoider of formulae; he refrains from statements which
pretend to be literally true; he finds fact nowhere and approximation
always.« (TS Eliot, Knowledge and Experience, p.163)
Eliot’s
pursuit of poetry can be seen as the pursuit of openness not through
closure but through the evasion of closure. A total evasion of closure
would be silence so instead Eliot offers us insights only to undermine
them. We find ourselves on the cusp of openness and closure and Eliot
in his poetry both reflects and explores that cusp.
Eliot
does
not describe openness but reaches out towards its character by
constructing a text that does not allow us to hold any particular
closure. Allowing the text to remain open with seemingly precise
descriptions, at least in so far as it is open. A similar experience
can be achieved by being silent, and without thought, and allowing the
world to wash over oneself. Most easily approached when we are alone
and in circumstances where differentiation of our experience is not
required or even easily achieved – facing out to sea, or
under a
night sky. At such points we have a sense of the wonder at the
strangeness of being alive and at the same time a sense of having
understood how things are, but it is an understanding without content,
a closure that is at once open.
As a philosopher,
Eliot tried
to describe this cusp of openness and closure saying: »Every
experience is a paradox in that it means to be absolute, and yet is
relative; in that it somehow always goes beyond itself and yet never
escapes itself.« (Ibid, p.166)
As a non
realist poet Eliot
instead offers a description of this circumstance but one that is not
intended to be held and which defies attempts to do so.
Each
is perhaps a mirror image of the other. Both seek to describe the cusp
of openness and closure: one from a perspective of the literal and the
pursuit of closure; the other from a perspective of the poetic and the
pursuit of openness.
V
The
notion of understanding
and knowledge is so close to us, so embedded in two millennia of
western culture, that we have forgotten how strange the idea is. Our
language, our stories about the world, our closures and in particular
our linguistic closures, help us intervene in the world, help us
achieve our aims and purposes. They are not thereby a description of
the world nor is their usefulness and success, if we wish to call it
that, dependent on their being true in a realist sense. We usually
assume that our closures accurately depict the world but so long as
they are effective we do not insist that the closures are complete, are
capable of exhausting the openness of the world even if we have a
specific and precise task. An engineer building a bridge will require
the closures used to be effective, and will assume that they are an
accurate depiction of the world. The engineer will be meticulous in
identifying any weaknesses in the closures used to describe the project
that might undermine its success, but the engineer is not concerned to
complete closure, to define for example what the bridge really is, or
the nature of force. The only concern is that the calculations and
description of the project enable effective intervention. Limitations
in the closures employed are to be ignored – unless they
threaten
the project. The aim is not to know the world but to intervene
effectively.
In contrast, when we look for
understanding we seek
a final and complete closure. To look for understanding is to look for
an endpoint, a place from which no further discussion, no further
exploration, needs to take place. It is a safe haven, a place where we
can rest knowing that there are no further surprises, that there is
nothing we have overlooked. No such safe haven is however possible and
in this sense understanding must elude us. At the moment when we think
we have understood how things are we have failed to do so, because our
understanding is in the context of closure and offers a discrete set of
identities, while the world is not a thing or set of things, but is
open.
In so far as philosophy attempts to help us
intervene
successfully it can operate within the literal and identify effective
closures and thereby refine its theories. In this respect it operates
as a metascience. In so far as philosophy seeks to describe how things
ultimately are, to provide an understanding of the world and our place
in it, the literal is inadequate and revision and refinement of its
literal theories will only make more apparent its failure. For the
pursuit of closure serves merely to bring to the fore the residual gap
between openness and closure, which on examination turns out to be not
less than everything. (Could it be that this is the core of the dispute
between so called analytic philosophy – which wants to make
progress in our dealings with the world and function as a metascience,
and continental philosophy which seeks an understanding of what it is
to be human? The first set of questions can be addressed with theory
while the latter is not reducible to the literal.)
This
is not
however an all or nothing choice. Nor could it be given we find
ourselves on the cusp of openness and closure, given that the literal
is poetic and the poetic literal. We choose where to place the balance.
Philosophy is surely on the one hand concerned with understanding and
starts out as an attempt to say how things ultimately are, to describe
as Rorty would have it the really real, even if it ends up uncovering
the impossibility of this attempt. It can also be an attempt to provide
a workable theory of our circumstances that might help us operate in
the world. While poetry may be appropriate to the metaphysical goal of
understanding it is not going to offer a workable theory to help us
intervene in the world.
Perhaps the quality of good
philosophy
is that it presents a workable theory but at the same time presses on
the theory sufficiently for its failures to become apparent and to
accept and adopt those failures as an essential element of
understanding and thereby come closer to saying how things are. I think
a good case could be made that Nietzsche, Wittgenstein, Heidegger,
Rorty and Derrida are all examples. And in this light I am beginning to
wonder whether my own attempts to rework the tradition in the framework
of openness and closure at times made it look as if the theory was more
watertight than it might have been. I ended Closure with the sentence:
»This book, this epilogue, this sentence, are attempts to
offer
(just such) a temporary form of abode – a means of holding
the
world that has the appearance of holding fast that which cannot be held
at all.« It is a sentiment that could perhaps have been more
apparent in the remainder of the seemingly literal text. But then with
my scientist hat I wanted a workable theory and I was excited by the
potential it seemed to offer.
The presentation of a
workable
theory if presented as such, as a workable theory, has its value. The
closer the theory appears to be to a consistent account of the whole
the more at risk is the enterprise of failure. For, as the philosopher
closes the system the enterprise fails. Non realist philosophers are
usually sufficiently swift footed to have spotted this danger and to
have drawn attention to the limitation of the theory. There is the
further risk however that by identifying the constraint the philosopher
imagines the opening has been left. In my own case I proposed that the
closure of the theory was itself held open because closure contains
openness. The neatness of this formulation is perhaps its weakness. It
is not good enough to speak about openness. The text itself must remain
open, must itself avoid seeming to offer too tightly refined a closure
which has the illusion of having captured an understanding of how
things are. For in that moment any such understanding has been lost.
In
so far as philosophers seek understanding, seek a means of catching
sight of where we ultimately are, Eliot’s version of the
poetic
strategy looks compelling. Perhaps in this sense all philosophical
insight into the nature of the world is necessarily poetic. Perhaps the
metaphysical task of philosophy is to write the insights of poetry as
prose. In so far as they are insights, and in so far as they can be
written. Yet in the moment of having caught sight of where we stand we
have lost our way. As we circle the space that would be the truth we
falter in the moment of our arrival.
Let me leave
Eliot with the last word. For somehow he seems always to have been
there before and to such greater effect.
And what there is to conquer
By strength and submission, has
already been discovered
Once or twice, or several times, by
men whom one cannot hope
To emulate – but there is
no competition –
There is only the fight to recover
what has been lost
And found and lost again and again: and
now, under conditions
That seem unpropitious.
Note
A
version of this paper was presented to a conference
›Philosophical Poets‹ organised by Nicholas Bunnin, Simon
Critchley, Katerina
Deligiorgi and Ulrich Schoedlbauer for the Forum for European
Philosophy and the Centre for Literature and Philosophy, University of
Sussex on 9 February 2008. Further information about the Forum for
European Philosophy can be found on the website:
www.philosophy-forum.org. Further information about the Centre for Literature and Philosophy can be found on the website
www.sussex.ac.uk/clp/.