Katerina Deligiorgi
______________
Philosophy and Mercy:
Self-Knowledge in Cavell and Auden
Philosophical discussions about philosophical style are rare.
Reluctance to engage with the topic suggests uncertainty about its
philosophical substance. The position, articulated in
characteristically trenchant manner by Bertrand Russell, that
»every philosophical problem, when it is subjected to the
necessary analysis and purification, is found either to be not really
philosophical at all, or else …logical« (Russell,
Our Knowledge of the External World, London 1914, p.42.) bars the
exploration of style from the range of philosophically useful or
appropriate pursuits. Style is what is scrubbed off once the work of
analysis is done. This conception of style as extraneous matter and, as
such, fundamentally dispensable comes to grief when one encounters a
work which resists ›purification‹, a work in
which the argument can be reached only by attending to its manner of
presentation. In this essay, I want to discuss such a work, Stanley
Cavell’s The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein,
Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy. I will conduct part of the
discussion indirectly by turning to a poetic work, W. H.
Auden’s The Sea and the Mirror: A Commentary on
Shakespeare’s The Tempest. The aim of the paper is
to uncover something about the distinctive type of knowledge that is
conveyed through engagement with style and requires for its
communication the achievement of a degree of self-knowledge.
One
of the striking features of Cavell’s prose is its
performatory character. The writing carries the weight of the
philosophical tasks of the book and so it is integral to its
philosophical substance. This has led early readers to conclude that
the work eludes paraphrase, and that it is best seen as situated
halfway between poetry and philosophy. How can we then approach such a
book? We can begin by seeking to discover the philosophical concerns
that guide Cavell’s stylistic choices. Style contains an
important clue since one of the things Cavell does in this book is show
his readers the limits of a certain kind of philosophical writing, a
writing that is guided by a conception of philosophy as a set of
problems. Problems raise expectations of solutions, which, on
Cavell’s account, are misplaced. The overweening ambition of
philosophy feeds on sceptical questions that are unconquerable and
present a flawed view of our intellectual and practical tasks. The
alternative Cavell proposes is to understand philosophy as »a
set of texts«. (Stanley Cavell, The Claim of Reason.
Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy, Oxford 1979, p. 3, henceforth CR) What this means is not given at the
outset but is left for the reader to discover by example, by following
Cavell’s own reading of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical
Investigations. So we get an idea of philosophy as text
through reading a philosophical text that is itself a reading of a
philosophical text. This is no mere exercise in hermeneutic ingenuity.
The matter that concerns Cavell is »that the human
creature’s basis in the world as a whole is not what we think
of as knowing« (CR 241). The failure of sceptically motivated
inquiries into truth hints at what Cavell calls the ›truth
of scepticism‹ namely that our relation to our world and our
relation to each other is not primarily or fundamentally cognitive. The
failure of such cognitive efforts discloses a moral landscape that is
out of kilter and which Cavell wants to bring to our attention. He does
so by incorporating in his reading of Wittgenstein readings of
Shakespeare. He is »pushed to pieces of
literature«, he explains, because of the way they present to
us »the problem of the other« (CR 476-7). This
literary presentation of the problem is also a kind of knowledge. So if
we are to engage with The Claim of Reason, a work
of philosophy that is also about the limits of philosophy, we must find
a way of getting hold of both its criticism of ›what we
think of as knowing‹ and the knowledge it seeks to provide
us with. Since this last is given through literary exemplification, it
is quite fitting that as philosophical readers we expand our range of
texts to discuss a literary text that meets Cavell’s
philosophical concerns from the other side so to speak, W. H.
Auden’s The Sea and the Mirror: A Commentary on
Shakespeare’s The Tempest.
In
the Shakespeare lectures he gave at the New School for Social Research
in 1947, Auden remarked that in The Sea and the Mirror
he was »attempting something which in a way is absurd, to
show in a work of art, the limitations of art«. (W.H. Auden,
The Sea and the Mirror. A Commentary on Shakespeare’s The
Tempest, edited by Arthur Kirsch, Princeton & Oxford 2003, p.xi, henceforth Kirsch) Written from 1942 to 1944, the
poem is the fruit of Auden’s sustained engagement with
Shakespeare’s work. Auden’s poetic commentary, his
reading, we might say, of The Tempest, gives voice
to the sceptical truth of Shakespeare’s play. The play ends
its story of magic and disillusion by breaking the spell it has on its
audience, Prospero addresses us directly and entreating us to show our
appreciation by applauding. And yet, having seen how enchantments fade,
we are given no safe conduct to a terra firma; the
»baseless fabric« of the theatrical vision lingers.
(Edward Mendelson, ed., W. H. Auden. Selected Poems London 1979,
henceforth SP) Auden’s poem draws attention to its poetic
fabric first by shifting poetic forms and then finally in the last
chapter by switching from poetry to prose. This is no empty play: style
is put to the task of telling a story of disillusion, of puncturing the
ambition of a conception of poetry that does not countenance failure
and measures its seriousness by its determination to be important. The
Sea and the Mirror is serious and ambitious by performing its
own limitations for the reader. The poem overreaches itself and
collapses into prose, a prose that thematises the problem of embodiment
indirectly by speaking of the illusory character of art. But because in
reading this we are still reading, we are still within the poem,
artistic illusion contains a promise of emancipation from fantasies of
humanity and hints at the possibility of a return to a human life that
is more human, or what Auden calls ›mercy‹.
What
I hope to show in this essay is that Cavell’s question is
›how do we get from philosophy to mercy?‹. This,
however, as Cavell, half-acknowledges, is an impossible question. I
want to suggest that his poetic-literary-philosophical approach still
betrays anxiety to avoid failure. This is what motivates the turn to
Auden’s poem. The poem-commentary explicitly thematises
failure and thus shows us how such an impossible question might be
approached and, in the end, left behind.
1.
Philosophical style and the problem of scepticism
The
Claim of Reason is a demanding book; it requires that the
reader finds her way round a stylistically unfamiliar philosophical
environment. Instead of clear statements of problems and procedures
that might lead to their solution (or clarifications that might lead to
their dissolution), we find digression, allusion, metaphor, citation,
repetition. The deliberate thwarting of the philosophical
reader’s expectations can be frustrating. Anthony Kenny in
his review of The Claim of Reason concluded that
»Despite Cavell’s philosophical and literary gifts
the book is a misshapen, undisciplined amalgam of ill assorted parts
…. The exasperated reader might well put the book down and
go no further«. (Cited in Mulhall, p. 1.) We can see in
Kenny’s exasperation an expression of the limits set by a
philosophical tradition premised on the pursuit of communicative
transparency. Yet exasperation is also a sign of reading. It can
therefore be seen also as an expression of the effort Cavell demands of
his reader. Wittgenstein advised: »Anything your reader can
do for himself leave to him.« (Wittgenstein, Culture and
Value, Peter Winch trans., Oxford 1980, p. 77) Cavell gives his reader a
lot to do.
In time, the initial experience of
style as hindering our understanding is transformed into an experience
of being guided into a different way of looking at certain traditional
philosophical problems. The philosophically trained reader who turns to
the final and largest section of the book, Scepticism and the
Problem of Others, is confronted with the chapter-heading
»Between Acknowledgement and Avoidance«. The
re-phrasing of the familiar problem ›of other
minds‹ as a problem of ›others‹ hints
at the transformation of an epistemic into an ethical problem and
prepares the reader for Cavell’s diagnosis of the kind of
failure he calls ›avoidance‹. Cavell seeks both
to explicate and to further the Wittgensteinian project of bringing the
reader to recognise the »false views of the inner and of the
outer« that produce and sustain one another (CR 329).
Recognising what is false involves crucially for Cavell engaging in a
process of self-scrutiny and self-knowledge: the question
›who or what is the other?‹ — or
›is this in fact another?‹ — is tied to
the question »who or what am I, that I should be called upon
to testify to such a question?« (CR 429).
Given
this framework of interpretation, Cavell is able to discuss
Wittgenstein’s remarks on pain and privacy not as
contributions to epistemology, but rather as elements in the laborious
process of self-knowledge. Wittgenstein’s familiar argument
that pain is not a picture becomes thus transformed into a Rousseauean
diagnosis of the relation »between the soul and its
society« (CR 329). A key reference is
Wittgenstein’s discussion of pain as an image: »To
say that ›The picture of pain comes into the language-game
with the words ›Pain‹‹ is a
misunderstanding. The image of pain is no picture«.
(Wittgenstein, Philosophische Untersuchungen, Frankfurt/M. 1984, p.
375) The traditional sceptical problem of pain references alluded to
here drives a wedge between inner and outer. The quest for reliable
access to someone else’s inner state, for a clear and legible
›picture‹, gains its plausibility from the
conviction that one has privileged access to one’s own inner
states (to use a different vocabulary: self-objectification is a
condition for seeking the other as object). It is this conception of
the inner as a secret and private domain that concerns Cavell.
Elaborating on Wittgenstein’s remarks, he reminds his
audience of the expressive capacity of language and of bodies:
»My references to my pain are exactly expressions of pain
itself; and my words refer to my pain just because, or to the extent,
that they are (modified) expressions of it« (CR 342). To have
a body, he continues, is to be »condemned to expression, to
meaning« (CR 357). Wittgenstein’s observation that
›The human body is the best picture of the human
soul‹ is thus interpreted as a reminder of the publicity of
embodiment: »The body is the field of expression of the
soul«, Cavell states, »a human soul has
a body« (CR 356).
The sceptical problem,
however, is not simply dismissed as if it were a mere blunder. What
motivates epistemic doubt about pain references and about the inner
states of others is dissatisfaction with our social and socially
embodied being. Scepticism can then be seen as expressive of a desire
for disassociation from one another. Our »working knowledge
of one another’s (inner) lives can reach no further than our
(outward) expressions, and we have cause to be disappointed in these
expressions« (CR 341). Talk of a hidden but known inner, and
an observable but treacherous outer, is an expression of disappointed
communication. It is this disappointment that motivates the attempt
»to account for and protect our separateness …our
unwillingness or incapacity either to know or to be known«
(CR 369). The truth of the ›private language
fantasy‹, Cavell argues, is that no language can fathom our
privateness, no account can be given of our separeteness: »We
are endlessly separate, for no reason«
(CR 369). ›No reason‹ can mean that there is no
convincing philosophical story we can tell about separateness - that it
is a pseudo-problem. It can also mean that it is a dumb thing, unworthy
of reason, this separateness of ours; or that there are no good reasons
for separateness, but plenty of bad ones. In each case, our sceptical
doubts and our attempts to refute them tell of »how private
we are, metaphysically and practically« (CR 370). But we just
saw that we ›have cause‹ to be disappointed by
our outward expressions. Are not failures of communication reason
enough for separateness? What Cavell suggests is that the
cause of the problem is no reason: to think that disappointed
communication is reason for separateness is to enter the (fantastical)
quest for a better more secure foundation for relating to one another.
But this, Cavell tells us, is already to take a wrong path, for we are
not facing a problem about knowledge or its absence. Our alienation
from ourselves, which has as its symptom our search for a soul that is
utterly secret and has a mysterious relation to our bodies, is itself a
symptom of our alienation from our shared humanity: »to be
human is to be one of humankind, to bear an internal relation to all
others« (CR 376).
If the issue is
avoidance, the practical and metaphysical isolation that motivates the
(misguided) search for potent anti-sceptical arguments, then clearly it
cannot be addressed in the manner of traditional epistemology. The
latter enters into it but only to the extent that the reader can be
made to see that the problem is not knowledge but what Cavell calls
›acknowledgement‹. The question is how best this
problem can be addressed. As he often does in the course of The
Claim of Reason, Cavell turns to literature to show how
acknowledgement might be expressed:
What is it men
in women do require
The lineaments of Gratified Desire
What
is it women do in men require
The lineaments of Gratified
Desire
(William Blake, The Question Answered, in Michael Mason
ed., William Blake, Oxford 1988, p. 265, quoted in CR 471)
Blake’s
lyric, Cavell comments, speaks of a »brave acceptance of the
sufficiency of human finitude«, its symmetrical structure
intimates a perfect reciprocity and complete disappearance of
disappointment in oneself and in others (CR 471). By contrast, the
depth of our dissatisfaction with our finitude is measured by the
degree of certainty we imagine would be sufficient to render us immune
to our philosophically manufactured, hyperbolic doubts. In drawing the
limits of the philosophical quest for knowledge, Cavell also draws the
limits of a certain way of doing philosophy. From the perspective he
seeks to open for us, the question ›Are you in
pain?‹ is a question too many. When he says that
»the crucified human body is our best expression of the human
soul« (CR 430), he is not just stating in the negative
Wittgenstein’s ›the human body is the best picture
of the human soul‹. He is also saying that avoidance too has
a picture: a picture of suffering. The deeper philosophical problem
about pain references is that we might observe the sighs, the tears and
the clenched teeth, and continue to seek confirmation of the
other’s pain. This route will not bring epistemic success but
frustration. Cavell makes the point by inviting us to see Othello as
embodying the »madness and bewitchment of
inquisitors« (CR 469). Othello’s ›rage
for proof‹ leads to Desdemona’s and to his own
death. »A statue, a stone is something whose existence is
fundamentally open to the ocular proof …A human being is
not« and the dead bodies of Desdemona and Othello
»form an emblem of this fact, the truth of
scepticism«(CR 495). The truth of scepticism is shown here as
a tragic and wholly self-inflicted failure of acknowledgement.
Philosophical
dreams of absolute certainty and of intellectual impeccability are,
Cavell suggests, analogously self-inflicted failures for which there is
no clear remedy:
So we are here, knowing they are
›gone to hell‹, she with a lie on her lips,
protecting him, he with her blood on him. Perhaps Blake has what he
calls songs to win them back with, to make room for hell in a juster
city. But can philosophy accept them back at the hands of poetry?
Certainly not so long as philosophy continues, as it has from the
first, to demand the banishment of poetry from its republic. Perhaps it
could if it could itself become literature. But can philosophy become
literature and still know itself? (CR 495).
2.
Self-knowledge as a philosophical problem
The
concluding questions of The Claim of Reason are
puzzling and provocative. What Cavell presents as the truth of
scepticism is the human capacity for inhumanity. This is a heavy
charge. Elsewhere Cavell specifies that he is not concerned with any
single sceptical argument but rather with »that radical doubt
or anxiety expressed in Descartes and in Hume, and in Kant’s
determination to transcend them, about whether we can know that the
world exists and I and others in it«. (Stanley Cavell,
Emerson, Coleridge, Kant, in John Rajchman and Cornel West, eds.,
Post-analytic Philosophy, New York 1985, p. 84) One may well come to
see such doubts as professional deformations of the philosopher and
dismiss them as »cold, and strain’d, and
ridiculous« and turn to the practical engagements that dispel
these clouds. (David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, L. A.
Selby-Bigge ed., Oxford 1949, p.269) But this wholesomely limpid
everyday is not the antidote we might expect. Alienating, hyperbolic
philosophical doubt is allied to familiar, ordinary puzzles. Another of
Blake’s lyrics, which Cavell does not cite, makes the point
succinctly:
When a man has married a wife he finds
out whether
Her knees and elbows are only glued together.
(Blake,
When a man has married a wife, in Mason, p. 280)
Blake’s
words speak directly of our endless fascination with our kind, one
another, our embodiment, the inner and outer that our bodies endow us
with. Curiosity about who we are, and how others are, and how the world
is feeds our skeptical doubts without turning us into murderous
inquisitors.
The hyperbole in Cavell’s
diagnosis can be seen as part of his argument: the challenge he
presents us with is to confront scepticism as a practical matter without
forfeiting the philosophical demand for self-knowledge. We are not
offered a choice between the ordinary labours of living and the
splenetic exertions of philosophising. Leaving philosophy for a
putatively untroubled everyday is to pile dreams upon dreams. The real
question is about the possibilities of self-knowledge. This is where
the issue arises again of how to proceed philosophically or indeed
whether there is such a thing as philosophical self-knowledge. Here the
textual evidence is ambiguous. We might be tempted to say that
Cavell’s writing has brought philosophy to a certain
self-knowledge about its tasks and its limits and that his readers
might possibly come to see certain things about their own philosophical
ways. But at the same time, Cavell is »pushed to pieces of
literature« (CR 476) as if philosophical self-knowledge runs
always the danger of turning to a problem about knowledge and a problem
about the self and a problem about others. His final remarks suggest
that as long as it is in pursuit of its own dream of self-grounding and
of full self-accounting, philosophy is unable to accept gifts and
treats poetic gifts with great suspicion. For philosophy to accept a
gift it is to accept its limits. To do this involves, among other
things, to acknowledge its traditional other, poetry. This is possible,
Cavell hints, if philosophy »could become
literature« (CR 495). Yet clearly, to acknowledge someone is
not to become this someone; Blake’s image of perfect
reciprocity, quoted earlier, is not a tautology. So for philosophy to
acknowledge poetry it does not need to become literature. Indeed, we
have been reading The Claim of Reason precisely as
a philosophical work of poetic acknowledgement. So what are we to make
of Cavell’s final question?
»Addressing
philosophy as literature«, Arthur Danto writes, »is
not meant to stultify the aspiration to philosophical truth so much as
to propose a caveat against a reduced concept of reading«.
(Philosophy as/and/of Literature, in: Rajchman and West, p. 67) There
is of course a long philosophical tradition in which philosophy is not
presented as a series of propositions to readers. James
Conant describes this tradition as one »in which the form of
the philosophical text is thought to be integral to its purpose. The
form of the text is modelled on a process of discovery«.
(Kierkegaard Wittgenstein and Nonsense, in Ted Cohen, Paul Guyer and
Hilary Putnam eds., Pursuits of Reason, Lubbock 1992, p. 195) The
reader’s relation to such philosophical texts can be captured
thus: »something is intended to happen to the reader other
than, or in addition to, being informed«, this
»something« can be described as
»acquiescence in a certain form of initiation and
life«. (Danto, ibid, 67) To engage in philosophy in this
manner, that is, to engage in it as a kind of activity, requires that
the reader responds not only to what is said but to how it is said. It
is by attending to the performatory aspect of the text – or
what we called ›style‹ - that the reader becomes
fully engaged. But this means that the reader attends to something that
affects the argument which is not an argument. Following Alex
Garcìa-Düttmann one want to speak here of the basic
›good luck‹ in which the author puts his trust to
get his argument through. (Düttmann, Arte fortunata
– un ›divertimento‹. Adorno,
›l’arte delle arti‹, Iride XVIII:44
(2005), pp. 157-163) Good luck, of course, is not something one can
force, nor count on in advance. Cavell’s concluding question
appears both to articulate this difficulty (›can philosophy
become literature?‹) and to throw into doubt the
possibilities of self-knowledge that this kind of philosophical writing
afford us (›…and still know itself?‹).
Another way of putting this is that serious communication, what Cavell
calls philosophical education at the start of the book, may be
impossible. (CR 124). The final question of the book is an expression
of uncertainty, perhaps doubt, about the books own
possibility. It is with this in mind that we may now to turn
to a work that ends not with doubt about its possibility but with full
admission of failure, yet this admission becomes a condition for a new
set of possibilities.
3.
Estrangement and conditions of mercy
The
Sea and the Mirror is Auden’s poetic commentary on The
Tempest. Prospero’s address to Ariel takes up
Chapter I, then the other characters identified by their distinctive
poetic idiom - sonnet, terza rima, sestina, villanelle (this last,
notoriously tricky, form is the voice of Miranda) speak their parts in
Chapter II. Caliban breaks his silence in Chapter III addressing the
imagined audience of the play, and the readers of the poem in prose.
Commentary on the poem tends to focus on Auden’s
philosophical explorations and on the way these shape his reading of The
Tempest. What interests me here is the way The Sea
and the Mirror articulates a poetic drama of self-knowledge,
which culminates in the final self-recognition of audience and author
that brings about a resolution of the problem of poetic self-knowledge
and its limits. In a letter to Christopher Isherwood, Auden commented
that his characters are ‘on the sea (ie living existentially)
but they have looked in the mirror’ (Kirsch 82). This
‘looking in the mirror’ of the characters is
presented as a process of self-alienation, meaning both estrangement
from self and letting-go part of the self in a process of
transformation and finally self-knowledge. (Auden, W.H., Lectures on
Shakespeare, Ed. Arthur C. Kirsch, Princeton 2002, 303) At the same
time, this process encompasses the medium itself, so that poetry and
its own transformative possibilities are at issue. The acknowledgement
of the limits of poetry becomes a condition of poetic release.
The
pivotal passage occurs in Capter III, where following a sudden change
of register, we discover that the audience fail to applaud at the
conclusion of Auden’s retelling of the story. Breaking our
expectations as readers of poetry, Auden has Caliban addressing
directly the audience, speaking their and our thoughts, in order to
diagnose our unease and finally release us. In the final soliloquy the
readers of the poem see themselves as the audience of the play, who see
themselves in the words of the actors, who are but poetic reflections
of the author who looks thus back on himself and on the very process of
self-reflection. This complex play of mirrors takes its cue from
Shakespeare. In the Epilogue of The Tempest,
Prospero addresses directly the audience, inviting them to applaud:
But
release me from my bands
With the help of your good hands.
…As
you from crimes would pardon’d be,
Let your
indulgence set me free.
(Shakespeare, The Tempest, in: C. H.
Hereford ed., The Works of Shakespeare, vol. IV London 1902, Epilogue,
ll 9-10, 19-20, p. 494)
In Auden’s poem,
there is no release. At the play’s end, players and audience
remain captive. There is no pardon or mercy. Fittingly, it is Caliban
who takes the stage to address the audience: »Now it is over.
No we have not dreamed it. Here we really stand, down stage with red
faces and no applause« (SP 173). In fastidious and elaborate
prose, he breaks with the poetic idiom of the other characters. We are
outside the poem, but not quite. Caliban puts the audience on the spot,
speaks their thoughts – ›the begged
question‹ – and, at the same time, responds to
their ›bewildered cry‹ their dissatisfaction, and
disappointment:
We must own (for the
present I speak your echo) to a nervous perplexity not
unmixed, frankly, with downright resentment. How can we grant the
indulgence for which in his epilogue your personified type of the
creative so lamely, tamely pleaded? Imprisoned, by you, in the mood
doubtful, loaded, by you, with distressing embarrassments, we are, we
submit, in no position to set anyone free (SP 149).
This
admission of impotence that the poet magician –
›your personified type of the creative‹
– deals in smoke and mirrors fails to satisfy the audience
for it suggests that in a tangle of illusion no-one has the power to
set anyone free. The players cannot be released, if the audience does
not applaud. But the audience cannot applaud because they are
themselves ›imprisoned‹. And their captivity is
made the more embarrassing by Caliban’s direct address.
What
holds up the release of the audience? In other words, what is it that
feeds the ›mood doubtful‹? Let us see what they
witnessed so far. One way of looking at the poetic peripeteia
of Auden’s characters is in terms of the trials of
self-knowledge. In Auden’s hands the characters achieve
self-knowledge by experiencing the loss of what they come to see as
dreams, illusions, follies, and fantasies. We could say that the poem
is made up of a series of discoveries of different kinds of avoidance,
different ways of being private or of experiencing how private we are
metaphysically and practically. Here is Gonzalo, counsillor of
‘doubt and insufficient love’:
There
was nothing to explain
Had I trusted the Absurd
And
straightforward note by note
Sung exactly what I
heard…
All would have begun to dance
Jigs
of self-deliverance (SP 139, 140).
Here is his
master, Alonso ›once King of Naples‹ advising his
son:
Only your darkness can tell you what
A
prince’s ornate mirror dare not …
Learn
from your dreams what you lack,
For as your fears are, so you
must hope
The Way of Justice is a tightrope’ (SP
142).
Alonso’s advice comes out of his own
acceptance of the Island’s magic, »where flesh and
mind/ Are delivered from mistrust« (SP 143). But perhaps the
most powerful expression of this experience is to be found in Prospero.
Prospero recounts his awakening into life as »a sobbing
dwarf« and confesses that »I was not what I
seemed« and that he used his magic to »blot out for
ever/ The gross insult of being one among many« (SP 130).
Freedom comes with a new self-knowledge:
Now,
Ariel, I am that I am, your late and lonely master,
Who knows
now what magic is: – the power to enchant
That comes
from disillusion (SP 130).
As he awakes into the
human life that is given him, he awakes also to his finitude:
And suddenly now, and for the first time, am cold
sober
With all my unanswered wishes and unwashed days
Stacked
up all around my life; as if through the ages I had dreamed
About
some tremendous journey I was taking,
…..And
now in my old age, I wake, and this journey really exists,
And
I have actually to take it (SP 134).
As each
character lets go their dreams, they each bid us farewell, leaving the
stage ready for Caliban.
It has been argued that
Auden is a poet of the ›divided consciousness‹, a
condition Auden himself describes: »Man’s being is
a copulative relation between a subject ego and a predicate
self«. (The Enchafed Flood, cited in Herbert, p. 6) The
characters in the passages just quoted embark on the process of
self-knowledge that allows them to get to grips with being a self that
is both subject and predicate, something »given, already
there in the world, finite, derived, along with, related and comparable
to other beings« (ibid). The anxiety of not being one among
many, of not being deceived, of not being loved dissipates as each
character awakes from their dreams of savvy, glory and power.
Still,
our witness of these different journeys to self-knowledge does not
suffice and does not satisfy. Our dissatisfaction, which manifests
itself in the incapacity to applaud, is also a sign that we share in
the players’ captivity. Caliban renders this implicit
self-knowledge explicit:
Our shame, our fear, our
incorrigible staginess, all wish and no resolve, are still, and more
intensely than ever, all we have: only now it is not in spite of them
but with them that we are blessed by the Wholly Other Life from which
we are separated by an essential emphatic gulf of which our contrived
fissures of mirror and proscenium arch – we understand them
at last – are feebly figurative signs, so that all our
meanings are reversed and it is precisely in its negative image of
Judgment that we can positively envisage mercy; it is just here, among
the ruins and the bones, that we may rejoice in the perfected Work
which is not ours. … the sounded note is the restored
relation. (SP 173-4).
If the condition for release
is self-knowledge, then this is as near to self-knowledge as we
– actors and audience – can come. The indulgence
demanded of the audience is at the same time a demand that the audience
recognise the shared failure and reciprocal entailments of granting
pardon: »Everything, the massacres, the whippings, the lies,
the twaddle, and all their carbon copies are still present«
(SP 173). The negative judgement the audience delivers by failing to
applaud forms part of its self-recognition, in that it is also a
negative judgement on itself, an acknowledgement of
its own shame, fear and incorrigible staginess. The failure to applaud
is then a kind of self-knowledge. But if self-knowledge is possible,
then release is possible. It is in the mutual recognition of captivity
that the possibility of mutual deliverance takes shape, or, in
Caliban’s words, it is in the ›negative image of
Judgement‹, the withheld applause, that we can
›positively envisage mercy‹.
Significantly,
the applause is still withheld. After all, it is not absorption in the
play that shall deliver us of our various illusions. Caliban hints at
the limits of this drama of self-knowledge and of mutual
acknowledgement when he describes the predicament of the dramatist:
»Having learnt his language I begin to feel something of the
serio-comic embarrassment of the dedicated dramatist, who in
representing to you your condition of estrangement from the truth is
doomed to fail the more he succeeds« (SP 171).
Caliban’s elaborate mode of address already marks a sobering
distance between players and audience, or poem and readers. This
distance allows us to reflect on how the desire for self-knowledge
— here, to see ourselves reflected in the words of the poem,
to recognise ourselves in the play — can itself be an
obstacle to self-knowledge. We can now re-interpret the final question
with which Cavell leaves his readers, as drawing our attention not to
the difficulties of philosophical acknowledgement, but to the
difficulties of self-knowledge. Caliban’s unsentimental
address to the audience articulates an attempt to emancipate us from
the poem, for which it is essential that we cease to recognise
ourselves in it. Put differently, by witnessing how poetry seeks to
exceed itself and thus finds its ambitions curtailed and shaped
prosaically, we are given a chance to learn something about illusion
and disillusion. To say, this is just a mirror, not the real thing, is
something we learn in the play but it is also a final
›negative image of Judgment’ in which
‘we can positively envisage mercy‹.
Note
A
version of this paper appeared in Literature and Aesthetics;
16:1(2006) pp.59-71, and a later version given in the Auden Centenary
conference organized by Dr J. D. Rhodes at the University of York (24
February 2007). I am grateful to the organizer and the audience for
comments on the earlier version.